- Dutch
- Frisian
- Saterfrisian
- Afrikaans
-
- Phonology
- Segment inventory
- Phonotactics
- Phonological processes
- Phonology-morphology interface
- Word stress
- Primary stress in simplex words
- Monomorphemic words
- Diachronic aspects
- Generalizations on stress placement
- Default penultimate stress
- Lexical stress
- The closed penult restriction
- Final closed syllables
- The diphthong restriction
- Superheavy syllables (SHS)
- The three-syllable window
- Segmental restrictions
- Phonetic correlates
- Stress shifts in loanwords
- Quantity-sensitivity
- Secondary stress
- Vowel reduction in unstressed syllables
- Stress in complex words
- Primary stress in simplex words
- Accent & intonation
- Clitics
- Spelling
- Morphology
- Word formation
- Compounding
- Nominal compounds
- Verbal compounds
- Adjectival compounds
- Affixoids
- Coordinative compounds
- Synthetic compounds
- Reduplicative compounds
- Phrase-based compounds
- Elative compounds
- Exocentric compounds
- Linking elements
- Separable complex verbs (SCVs)
- Gapping of complex words
- Particle verbs
- Copulative compounds
- Derivation
- Numerals
- Derivation: inputs and input restrictions
- The meaning of affixes
- Non-native morphology
- Cohering and non-cohering affixes
- Prefixation
- Suffixation
- Nominal suffixation: person nouns
- Conversion
- Pseudo-participles
- Bound forms
- Nouns
- Nominal prefixes
- Nominal suffixes
- -aal and -eel
- -aar
- -aard
- -aat
- -air
- -aris
- -ast
- Diminutives
- -dom
- -een
- -ees
- -el (nominal)
- -elaar
- -enis
- -er (nominal)
- -erd
- -erik
- -es
- -eur
- -euse
- ge...te
- -heid
- -iaan, -aan
- -ief
- -iek
- -ier
- -ier (French)
- -ière
- -iet
- -igheid
- -ij and allomorphs
- -ijn
- -in
- -ing
- -isme
- -ist
- -iteit
- -ling
- -oir
- -oot
- -rice
- -schap
- -schap (de)
- -schap (het)
- -sel
- -st
- -ster
- -t
- -tal
- -te
- -voud
- Verbs
- Adjectives
- Adverbs
- Univerbation
- Neo-classical word formation
- Construction-dependent morphology
- Morphological productivity
- Compounding
- Inflection
- Inflection and derivation
- Allomorphy
- The interface between phonology and morphology
- Word formation
- Syntax
- Preface and acknowledgements
- Verbs and Verb Phrases
- 1 Characterization and classification
- 2 Projection of verb phrases I:Argument structure
- 3 Projection of verb phrases II:Verb frame alternations
- Introduction
- 3.1. Main types
- 3.2. Alternations involving the external argument
- 3.3. Alternations of noun phrases and PPs
- 3.3.1. Dative/PP alternations (dative shift)
- 3.3.1.1. Dative alternation with aan-phrases (recipients)
- 3.3.1.2. Dative alternation with naar-phrases (goals)
- 3.3.1.3. Dative alternation with van-phrases (sources)
- 3.3.1.4. Dative alternation with bij-phrases (possessors)
- 3.3.1.5. Dative alternation with voor-phrases (benefactives)
- 3.3.1.6. Conclusion
- 3.3.1.7. Bibliographical notes
- 3.3.2. Accusative/PP alternations
- 3.3.3. Nominative/PP alternations
- 3.3.1. Dative/PP alternations (dative shift)
- 3.4. Some apparent cases of verb frame alternation
- 3.5. Bibliographical notes
- 4 Projection of verb phrases IIIa:Selection of clauses/verb phrases
- 5 Projection of verb phrases IIIb:Argument and complementive clauses
- Introduction
- 5.1. Finite argument clauses
- 5.2. Infinitival argument clauses
- 5.3. Complementive clauses
- 6 Projection of verb phrases IIIc:Complements of non-main verbs
- 7 Projection of verb phrases IIId:Verb clusters
- 8 Projection of verb phrases IV: Adverbial modification
- 9 Word order in the clause I:General introduction
- 10 Word order in the clause II:Position of the finite verb (verb-first/second)
- 11 Word order in the clause III:Clause-initial position (wh-movement)
- Introduction
- 11.1. The formation of V1- and V2-clauses
- 11.2. Clause-initial position remains (phonetically) empty
- 11.3. Clause-initial position is filled
- 12 Word order in the clause IV:Postverbal field (extraposition)
- 13 Word order in the clause V: Middle field (scrambling)
- 14 Main-clause external elements
- Nouns and Noun Phrases
- 1 Characterization and classification
- 2 Projection of noun phrases I: complementation
- Introduction
- 2.1. General observations
- 2.2. Prepositional and nominal complements
- 2.3. Clausal complements
- 2.4. Bibliographical notes
- 3 Projection of noun phrases II: modification
- Introduction
- 3.1. Restrictive and non-restrictive modifiers
- 3.2. Premodification
- 3.3. Postmodification
- 3.3.1. Adpositional phrases
- 3.3.2. Relative clauses
- 3.3.3. Infinitival clauses
- 3.3.4. A special case: clauses referring to a proposition
- 3.3.5. Adjectival phrases
- 3.3.6. Adverbial postmodification
- 3.4. Bibliographical notes
- 4 Projection of noun phrases III: binominal constructions
- Introduction
- 4.1. Binominal constructions without a preposition
- 4.2. Binominal constructions with a preposition
- 4.3. Bibliographical notes
- 5 Determiners: articles and pronouns
- Introduction
- 5.1. Articles
- 5.2. Pronouns
- 5.3. Bibliographical notes
- 6 Numerals and quantifiers
- 7 Pre-determiners
- Introduction
- 7.1. The universal quantifier al 'all' and its alternants
- 7.2. The pre-determiner heel 'all/whole'
- 7.3. A note on focus particles
- 7.4. Bibliographical notes
- 8 Syntactic uses of noun phrases
- Adjectives and Adjective Phrases
- 1 Characteristics and classification
- 2 Projection of adjective phrases I: Complementation
- 3 Projection of adjective phrases II: Modification
- 4 Projection of adjective phrases III: Comparison
- 5 Attributive use of the adjective phrase
- 6 Predicative use of the adjective phrase
- 7 The partitive genitive construction
- 8 Adverbial use of the adjective phrase
- 9 Participles and infinitives: their adjectival use
- 10 Special constructions
- Adpositions and adpositional phrases
- 1 Characteristics and classification
- Introduction
- 1.1. Characterization of the category adposition
- 1.2. A formal classification of adpositional phrases
- 1.3. A semantic classification of adpositional phrases
- 1.3.1. Spatial adpositions
- 1.3.2. Temporal adpositions
- 1.3.3. Non-spatial/temporal prepositions
- 1.4. Borderline cases
- 1.5. Bibliographical notes
- 2 Projection of adpositional phrases: Complementation
- 3 Projection of adpositional phrases: Modification
- 4 Syntactic uses of the adpositional phrase
- 5 R-pronominalization and R-words
- 1 Characteristics and classification
- Phonology
-
- General
- Phonology
- Segment inventory
- Phonotactics
- Phonological Processes
- Assimilation
- Vowel nasalization
- Syllabic sonorants
- Final devoicing
- Fake geminates
- Vowel hiatus resolution
- Vowel reduction introduction
- Schwa deletion
- Schwa insertion
- /r/-deletion
- d-insertion
- {s/z}-insertion
- t-deletion
- Intrusive stop formation
- Breaking
- Vowel shortening
- h-deletion
- Replacement of the glide w
- Word stress
- Clitics
- Allomorphy
- Orthography of Frisian
- Morphology
- Inflection
- Word formation
- Derivation
- Prefixation
- Infixation
- Suffixation
- Nominal suffixes
- Verbal suffixes
- Adjectival suffixes
- Adverbial suffixes
- Numeral suffixes
- Interjectional suffixes
- Onomastic suffixes
- Conversion
- Compositions
- Derivation
- Syntax
- Verbs and Verb Phrases
- Characteristics and classification
- Unergative and unaccusative subjects
- Evidentiality
- To-infinitival clauses
- Predication and noun incorporation
- Ellipsis
- Imperativus-pro-Infinitivo
- Expression of irrealis
- Embedded Verb Second
- Agreement
- Negation
- Nouns & Noun Phrases
- Classification
- Complementation
- Modification
- Partitive noun constructions
- Referential partitive constructions
- Partitive measure nouns
- Numeral partitive constructions
- Partitive question constructions
- Nominalised quantifiers
- Kind partitives
- Partitive predication with prepositions
- Bare nominal attributions
- Articles and names
- Pronouns
- Quantifiers and (pre)determiners
- Interrogative pronouns
- R-pronouns
- Syntactic uses
- Adjective Phrases
- Characteristics and classification
- Complementation
- Modification and degree quantification
- Comparison by degree
- Comparative
- Superlative
- Equative
- Attribution
- Agreement
- Attributive adjectives vs. prenominal elements
- Complex adjectives
- Noun ellipsis
- Co-occurring adjectives
- Predication
- Partitive adjective constructions
- Adverbial use
- Participles and infinitives
- Adposition Phrases
- Characteristics and classification
- Complementation
- Modification
- Intransitive adpositions
- Predication
- Preposition stranding
- Verbs and Verb Phrases
-
- General
- Morphology
- Morphology
- 1 Word formation
- 1.1 Compounding
- 1.1.1 Compounds and their heads
- 1.1.2 Special types of compounds
- 1.1.2.1 Affixoids
- 1.1.2.2 Coordinative compounds
- 1.1.2.3 Synthetic compounds and complex pseudo-participles
- 1.1.2.4 Reduplicative compounds
- 1.1.2.5 Phrase-based compounds
- 1.1.2.6 Elative compounds
- 1.1.2.7 Exocentric compounds
- 1.1.2.8 Linking elements
- 1.1.2.9 Separable Complex Verbs and Particle Verbs
- 1.1.2.10 Noun Incorporation Verbs
- 1.1.2.11 Gapping
- 1.2 Derivation
- 1.3 Minor patterns of word formation
- 1.1 Compounding
- 2 Inflection
- 1 Word formation
- Morphology
- Syntax
- Adjectives and adjective phrases (APs)
- 0 Introduction to the AP
- 1 Characteristics and classification of APs
- 2 Complementation of APs
- 3 Modification and degree quantification of APs
- 4 Comparison by comparative, superlative and equative
- 5 Attribution of APs
- 6 Predication of APs
- 7 The partitive adjective construction
- 8 Adverbial use of APs
- 9 Participles and infinitives as APs
- Nouns and Noun Phrases (NPs)
- 0 Introduction to the NP
- 1 Characteristics and Classification of NPs
- 2 Complementation of NPs
- 3 Modification of NPs
- 3.1 Modification of NP by Determiners and APs
- 3.2 Modification of NP by PP
- 3.3 Modification of NP by adverbial clauses
- 3.4 Modification of NP by possessors
- 3.5 Modification of NP by relative clauses
- 3.6 Modification of NP in a cleft construction
- 3.7 Free relative clauses and selected interrogative clauses
- 4 Partitive noun constructions and constructions related to them
- 4.1 The referential partitive construction
- 4.2 The partitive construction of abstract quantity
- 4.3 The numerical partitive construction
- 4.4 The partitive interrogative construction
- 4.5 Adjectival, nominal and nominalised partitive quantifiers
- 4.6 Kind partitives
- 4.7 Partitive predication with a preposition
- 4.8 Bare nominal attribution
- 5 Articles and names
- 6 Pronouns
- 7 Quantifiers, determiners and predeterminers
- 8 Interrogative pronouns
- 9 R-pronouns and the indefinite expletive
- 10 Syntactic functions of Noun Phrases
- Adpositions and Adpositional Phrases (PPs)
- 0 Introduction to the PP
- 1 Characteristics and classification of PPs
- 2 Complementation of PPs
- 3 Modification of PPs
- 4 Bare (intransitive) adpositions
- 5 Predication of PPs
- 6 Form and distribution of adpositions with respect to staticity and construction type
- 7 Adpositional complements and adverbials
- Verbs and Verb Phrases (VPs)
- 0 Introduction to the VP in Saterland Frisian
- 1 Characteristics and classification of verbs
- 2 Unergative and unaccusative subjects and the auxiliary of the perfect
- 3 Evidentiality in relation to perception and epistemicity
- 4 Types of to-infinitival constituents
- 5 Predication
- 5.1 The auxiliary of being and its selection restrictions
- 5.2 The auxiliary of going and its selection restrictions
- 5.3 The auxiliary of continuation and its selection restrictions
- 5.4 The auxiliary of coming and its selection restrictions
- 5.5 Modal auxiliaries and their selection restrictions
- 5.6 Auxiliaries of body posture and aspect and their selection restrictions
- 5.7 Transitive verbs of predication
- 5.8 The auxiliary of doing used as a semantically empty finite auxiliary
- 5.9 Supplementive predication
- 6 The verbal paradigm, irregularity and suppletion
- 7 Verb Second and the word order in main and embedded clauses
- 8 Various aspects of clause structure
- Adjectives and adjective phrases (APs)
-
- General
- Phonology
- Afrikaans phonology
- Segment inventory
- Overview of Afrikaans vowels
- The diphthongised long vowels /e/, /ø/ and /o/
- The unrounded mid-front vowel /ɛ/
- The unrounded low-central vowel /ɑ/
- The unrounded low-central vowel /a/
- The rounded mid-high back vowel /ɔ/
- The rounded high back vowel /u/
- The rounded and unrounded high front vowels /i/ and /y/
- The unrounded and rounded central vowels /ə/ and /œ/
- The diphthongs /əi/, /œy/ and /œu/
- Overview of Afrikaans consonants
- The bilabial plosives /p/ and /b/
- The alveolar plosives /t/ and /d/
- The velar plosives /k/ and /g/
- The bilabial nasal /m/
- The alveolar nasal /n/
- The velar nasal /ŋ/
- The trill /r/
- The lateral liquid /l/
- The alveolar fricative /s/
- The velar fricative /x/
- The labiodental fricatives /f/ and /v/
- The approximants /ɦ/, /j/ and /ʋ/
- Overview of Afrikaans vowels
- Word stress
- The phonetic properties of stress
- Primary stress on monomorphemic words in Afrikaans
- Background to primary stress in monomorphemes in Afrikaans
- Overview of the Main Stress Rule of Afrikaans
- The short vowels of Afrikaans
- Long vowels in monomorphemes
- Primary stress on diphthongs in monomorphemes
- Exceptions
- Stress shifts in place names
- Stress shift towards word-final position
- Stress pattern of reduplications
- Phonological processes
- Vowel related processes
- Consonant related processes
- Homorganic glide insertion
- Phonology-morphology interface
- Phonotactics
- Morphology
- Syntax
- Afrikaans syntax
- Nouns and noun phrases
- Characteristics of the NP
- Classification of nouns
- Complementation of NPs
- Modification of NPs
- Binominal and partitive constructions
- Referential partitive constructions
- Partitive measure nouns
- Numeral partitive constructions
- Partitive question constructions
- Partitive constructions with nominalised quantifiers
- Partitive predication with prepositions
- Binominal name constructions
- Binominal genitive constructions
- Bare nominal attribution
- Articles and names
- Pronouns
- Quantifiers, determiners and predeterminers
- Syntactic uses of the noun phrase
- Adjectives and adjective phrases
- Characteristics and classification of the AP
- Complementation of APs
- Modification and Degree Quantification of APs
- Comparison by comparative, superlative and equative degree
- Attribution of APs
- Predication of APs
- The partitive adjective construction
- Adverbial use of APs
- Participles and infinitives as adjectives
- Verbs and verb phrases
- Characterisation and classification
- Argument structure
- Verb frame alternations
- Complements of non-main verbs
- Verb clusters
- Complement clauses
- Adverbial modification
- Word order in the clause: Introduction
- Word order in the clause: position of the finite Verb
- Word order in the clause: Clause-initial position
- Word order in the clause: Extraposition and right-dislocation in the postverbal field
- Word order in the middle field
- Emphatic constructions
- Adpositions and adposition phrases
This section discusses wh-extraction from argument clauses. The examples in (322) show that such extractions can be applied to at least three types of phrases: wh-phrases, relative pronouns, and contrastively stressed phrases. For convenience, we will focus on extraction of wh-phrases, and refer the reader to Chapter 11 for a more extensive discussion of the different kinds of wh-movement.
a. | Wati | denk | je | [dat | Marie morgen ti | zal | vertellen]? | |
what | think | you | that | Marie tomorrow | will | tell | ||
'What do you think that Marie will tell tomorrow?' |
b. | Hij liep | naar de plaats | waari | hij | wist | [dat | zijn accordeon ti | stond]. | |
he walked | to the place | where | he | knew | that | his accordion | stood | ||
'He walked to the place where he knew his accordion was.' |
c. | Dit boeki | denk ik | [dat Marie ti | wel | wil | hebben]. | |
this book | think I | that Marie | prt | wants.to | have | ||
'This book, I think that Marie would like to have.' |
Argument clauses are special in that they allow wh-extraction under specific conditions. The examples in (323) show that the extracted wh-phrase may be either an argument of the embedded verb or an adjunct. The traces ti refer to the original position of the moved wh-phrases in the embedded clauses.
a. | Ik | denk [Clause | dat | Marie | dit boek | morgen | zal | kopen]. | |
I | think | that | Marie | this book | tomorrow | will | buy | ||
'I think that Marie will buy this book tomorrow.' |
b. | Wiei | denk | je [Clause | dat ti | dit boek | morgen | zal | kopen]? | subject | |
who | think | you | that | this book | tomorrow | will | buy | |||
'Who do you think will buy this book tomorrow?' |
c. | Wati | denk | je [Clause | dat | Marie ti | morgen | zal | kopen]? | object | |
what | think | you | that | Marie | tomorrow | will | buy | |||
'What do you think that Marie will buy tomorrow?' |
d. | Wanneeri | denk | je [Clause | dat | Marie dit boek ti | zal | kopen]? | adverbial | |
when | think | you | that | Marie this book | will | buy | |||
'When do you think that Marie will buy this book?' |
The fact that wh-phrases can be extracted from argument clauses is rather special as this is categorically prohibited from adjunct clauses. The examples in (324), for instance, show that conditional clauses are strong (absolute) islands for wh-movement; they block wh-extraction of both arguments and adjuncts.
a. | Jan | zal | blij | zijn [Clause | als | Marie dit boek | morgen | zal | kopen]. | |
Jan | will | happy | be | if | Marie this book | tomorrow | will | buy | ||
'Jan will be happy if Marie will buy this book tomorrow.' |
b. | * | Wiei | zal | Jan blij | zijn [Clause | als ti | dit boek | morgen | zal | kopen]? |
who | will | Jan happy | be | if | this book | tomorrow | will | buy |
c. | * | Wati | zal | Jan | blij | zijn [Clause | als | Marie ti | morgen | zal | kopen]? |
what | will | Jan | happy | be | if | Marie | tomorrow | will | buy |
d. | * | Wanneeri | zal | Jan blij | zijn [Clause | als | Marie dit boek ti | zal | kopen]? |
when | will Jan | happy | be | if | Marie this book | will | buy |
There are good reasons for assuming that the wh-phrases in (323) are not moved in one fell swoop into their target position but that this involves an additional movement step via the initial position of the embedded clause; cf. Section 11.3 and Chomsky (1973/1977). This is indicated in the structures in (325), in which the traces refer to the positions that the moved phrase has occupied during the derivation; the CP/TP structure of clauses assumed here is discussed in Section 9.1.
a. | Wiei | denk | je [CPti | dat [TPti | dit boek | zal | kopen]]? | |
who | think | you | that | this book | will | buy |
b. | Wati | denk | je [CPti | dat [TP | Marie ti | zal | kopen]]? | |
what | think | you | that | Marie | will | buy |
c. | Wanneeri | denk | je [CPti | dat [TP | Marie | dit boek ti | zal | kopen]]? | |
when | think | you | that | Marie | this book | will | buy |
The main reason for assuming that the wh-phrases are moved via the initial position of the embedded clause is that this immediately accounts for the unacceptability of examples like (326b&c); since the clause-initial position of the embedded clause is already occupied by the subject pronoun wie'who', wh-extraction of the object/adjunct must apply in one fell swoop and this is not allowed. Note that (326c) is acceptable when the adverb wanneer'when' is construed as a modifier of the matrix predicate, but the reading intended here is the one in which it modifies the embedded predicate dit boek kopen'buy this book', as is indicated by the traces.
a. | Jan vroeg [CP | wie C [TPti | dit boek | morgen | zal | kopen]]? | |
Jan asked | who | this book | tomorrow | will | buy | ||
'Jan asked who will buy this book tomorrow.' |
b. | * | Watj | vroeg | Jan [CP | wiei C [TPtitj | morgen | zal | kopen]]? |
what | asked | Jan | who | tomorrow | will | buy |
c. | * | Wanneerj | vroeg Jan [CP | wiei C [TPti | dit boek tj | zal | kopen]]? |
when | asked Jan | who | this book | will | buy |
Although more can be said about the restrictions on wh-movement (see Section 11.3.1), the above suffices for the main topic in this subsection: which verbs may function as bridge verbs, that is, allow wh-extraction from their argument clauses? For example, whereas verbs of saying/thinking normally license wh-extraction from their complement clause, verbs of manner of speech such as fluisteren'to whisper' normally do not; this observation is attributed by Erteschik-Shir (2006), to an unpublished paper by Janet Dean (Fodor) from 1967.
a. | Wati | zei | Jan [Clause | dat | Marie ti | gelezen | had]? | |
what | said | Jan | that | Marie | read | had | ||
'What did Jan say that Marie had read?' |
b. | ?? | Wati | fluisterde | Jan [Clause | dat | Marie ti | gelezen | had]? |
what | whispered | Jan | that | Marie | read | had | ||
'What did Jan whisper that Marie had read?' |
The examples in (328) show that irrealis verbs expressing a hope or a wish constitute another set of verbs that readily license wh-extraction in Dutch; cf. Haider (2010:108) for the same observation for those varieties of German that allow wh-extraction from embedded dass-clauses.
a. | Ik | hoop [Clause | dat | Marie | dit boek | morgen | zal | kopen]. | |
I | hope | that | Marie | this book | tomorrow | will | buy | ||
'I hope that Marie will buy this book tomorrow.' |
b. | Wiei | hoop | je [Clause | dat ti | dit boek | morgen | zal | kopen]? | subject | |
who | hope | you | that | this book | tomorrow | will | buy | |||
'Who do you hope will buy this book tomorrow?' |
c. | Wati | hoop | je [Clause | dat | Marie ti | morgen | zal | kopen]? | object | |
what | hope | you | that | Marie | tomorrow | will | buy | |||
'What do you hope that Marie will buy tomorrow?' |
d. | Wanneeri | hoop | je [Clause | dat | Marie dit boek ti | zal | kopen]? | adverbial | |
when | hope | you | that | Marie this book | will | buy | |||
'When do you hope that Marie will buy this book?' |
Factive verbs like betreuren'to regret', on the other hand, systematically seem to block wh-extraction from their complement clause given that examples like (329b-d) are generally judged to be unacceptable; see, e.g., Hoeksema (2006:147).
a. | Ik | betreur [Clause | dat | Marie | dit boek | morgen | zal | verkopen]. | |
I | regret | that | Marie | this book | tomorrow | will | sell | ||
'I regret that Marie will sell this book tomorrow.' |
b. | *? | Wiei | betreur | je [Clause | dat ti | dit boek | morgen | zal | verkopen]? | subject |
who | regret | you | that | this book | tomorrow | will | sell | |||
'Who do you regret will sell this book tomorrow?' |
c. | *? | Wati | betreur | je [Clause | dat | Marie ti | morgen | zal | verkopen]? | object |
what | regret | you | that | Marie | tomorrow | will | sell | |||
'What do you regret that Marie will sell tomorrow?' |
d. | * | Wanneeri | betreur | je [Clause | dat | Marie dit boek ti | zal verkopen]? | adverbial |
when | regret | you | that | Marie this book | will sell | |||
'When do you regret that Marie will sell this book?' |
Examples like (329b&c), in which an argument is extracted seem degraded but are often considered to be better than examples such as (329d), in which an adjunct is extracted. This so-called argument-adjunct asymmetry is often attributed to the referential status of arguments; see Rizzi (1990). That referential status is relevant is clear from the fact that argument extraction becomes even better when the argument is discourse-linked, that is, when the hearer is asked to pick some entity or set of entities from some presupposed list. Although there is considerable variation in acceptability judgments on examples of this type, some speakers even seem to consider them fully acceptable; see, e.g., Zwart (2011:209) for cases of object extraction. If acceptable, the examples in (330) show that factive clauses are not strong, but weak (selective) islands for wh-extraction.
a. | % | Welke studenti | betreur | je [Clause | dat ti | dit boek | zal | verkopen]? |
which student | regret | you | that | this book | will | sell | ||
'Which student do you regret will sell this book?' |
b. | % | Welk boeki | betreur | je [Clause | dat | Marie ti | zal | verkopen]? |
which book | regret | you | that | Marie | will | sell | ||
'Which book do you regret that Marie will sell?' |
All in all, the list of bridge verbs seems to be relatively small. Hoeksema (2006) collected a sample of such verbs selected from written sources published after 1780. The complete collection consists of 963 tokens and 110 types. Most types have a very low frequency: nearly fifty types occur only once. Restricting ourselves to types occurring minimally six times, we get the result in Table (331). Bridge verbs are not only relevant for wh-questions but also for relative clause and topicalization constructions.
begrijpen'to understand' | 18 | # | verzekeren'to assure' | 8 | |
beweren'to claim' | 9 | vinden'to consider/think' | 34 | ||
denken'to think' | 318 | voelen'to feel/think' | 9 | ||
geloven'to believe' | 29 | vrezen'to fear' | 10 | ||
hopen'to hope' | 37 | wensen'to wish' | 17 | ||
horen'to hear' | 7 | weten'to know' | 73 | # | |
menen'to suppose' | 62 | willen'to want' | 119 | ||
oordelen'to judge' | 7 | willen hebben 'would like' | 6 | ||
rekenen (meaning unclear) | 6 | # | zeggen'to say' | 59 | |
vermoeden'to suspect' | 15 | zich voorstellen'to imagine' | 8 | ||
vertrouwen'to trust' | 6 | zien'to see' | 18 | ||
verwachten'to expect' | 13 |
Since Hoeksema does not give his list of attested examples, we searched the internet with the string [Wat V[±past] je dat'what do/did you V that ...?' in order to check whether the verbs in Table (331) occur in the relevant type of wh-question. The three cases for which we could not find such examples are marked by a number sign; their use may be restricted to relative clause or topicalization constructions; see example (322b), for instance, which was taken from Hoeksema (2006). This leaves us with no more then twenty verbs that are regularly used as bridge verbs in wh-questions, and there is in fact only one verb, denken'to think', that is really frequent (>300 tokens). Another relatively frequent bridge verb is the irrealis verb willen'to want' (>100), but all other verbs are relatively infrequent (<100). Other corpus-based research has revealed a similar preference for the verb denken and, to a lesser extent, willen; cf. Verhagen (2005:119ff.) and Schippers (2012:105).
Wh-extraction has given rise to two main lines of research, which Erteschik-Shir (2006) refers to as, respectively, the structural and the semantic approach. We will start with arguments in favor of the structural approach, according to which bridge verbs have some special syntactic property that makes their complement clauses transparent for wh-movement. For example, Erteschik-Shir mentions that verbs of manner of speech such as fluisteren'to whisper' differ from verbs of speaking and thinking in that they can occur without a propositional clause, and she suggests on the basis of this that embedded clauses co-occurring with verbs of manner of speech may have a syntactic status different from embedded clauses that co-occur with verbs of speaking and thinking.
a. | Jan fluisterde/schreeuwde. | |
Jan whispered/yelled |
b. | Jan *zei/??dacht. | |
Jan said/thought |
More support for the structural approach comes from languages like English and German. In English, the set of bridge verbs seems to coincide more or less with the set of verbs allowing that-deletion in embedded declarative clauses, an observation again attributed by Erteschik-Shir (2006) to Janet Dean (Fodor). Verbs of speaking/thinking, for example, allow that-deletion while factive verbs like to regret do not (although it is not too hard to find cases on the internet). Since Dutch does not allow dat-deletion in embedded declarative clauses, we cannot provide similar evidence on the basis of this language.
a. | John thinks Marie will be elected Chair. |
b. | * | John regrets Marie will be elected Chair. |
As for German, Haider (1985:55) claims that most bridge verbs trigger embedded verb-second in the German varieties that have it (the Northern varieties as well as standard German), although irrealis verbs like mögen'to like' are an exception to this general rule; cf. Haider (2010:124, fn. 25). The examples in (334) show that wh-extraction even requires the embedded finite verb to be in second position in those varieties that do not allow wh-extraction from embedded declarative dass-clauses; wh-extraction in dialects not allowing a set-up such as in (334a) obligatorily triggers verb-second, as in (334b). Since Dutch does not have this form of embedded verb-second, we cannot provide similar evidence on the basis of this language.
a. | Auf weni | glaubte | man [CPti | dass[TP | sie ti | gewartet | habe]]? | Southern G. | |
for whom | believed | one | that | she | waited | has | |||
'For whom did people think that she has waited?' |
b. | Auf weni | glaubte | man [CPti [TP | habe | sie ti | gewartet thabe]]? | Northern G. | |
for whom | believed | one | has | she | waited | |||
'For whom did people think that she has waited?' |
In short, arguments in favor of the structural approach to wh-extraction emphasize that bridge verbs obligatorily take a complement clause and that, in some languages at least, such verbs may affect the form of these clauses by licensing complementizer deletion or embedded verb-second. The semantic approach, which originates in Erteschik-Shir's (1973) seminal work, emphasizes the effect of information structure on wh-extraction. The generalization is that wh-extraction is possible only from clauses which are focused, that is, which express the new information of the clause. This immediately accounts for the fact that wh-movement is normally not possible from factive clauses given that these present propositions the truth of which is presupposed by the speaker; see the discussion in Section 5.1.2.3. It may, however, also account for the contrast between the primeless and primed examples in (335b&c). That we are dealing with a so-called weak island is clear from the fact that the two primed examples exhibit the argument-adjunct asymmetry discussed in Subsection I. For completeness' sake, it should be noted that the intended reading of the two (c)-examples is the one in which the adverbial wanneer'when' modifies the embedded clause; matrix scope is not intended here.
a. | Jan zei | (niet) | [dat | Marie dat boek | gisteren | gekocht | had]. | |
Jan said | not | that | Marie that book | yesterday | bought | had | ||
'Jan said/didnʼt say that Marie had bought that book yesterday.' |
b. | Wati | zei | Jan | [dat | Marie ti | gisteren | gekocht | had]? | argument | |
what | said | Jan | that | Marie | yesterday | bought | had | |||
'What did Jan say that Marie had bought yesterday?' |
b'. | ?? | Wati | zei | Jan niet | [dat | Marie ti | gekocht | had]? |
what | said | Jan not | that | Marie | bought | had | ||
'What didnʼt Jan say that Marie had bought?' |
c. | Wanneeri | zei | Jan | [dat | Marie | dat boek ti | gekocht | had]? | adjunct | |
when | said | Jan | that | Marie | that book | bought | had | |||
'When did Jan say that Mary had bought the book?' |
c'. | * | Wanneeri | zei | Jan niet | [dat | Marie dat boek ti | gekocht | had]? |
when | said | Jan not | that | Marie that book | bought | had | ||
'*When didnʼt Jan say that Marie had bought the book?' |
Erteschik-Shir (1973:95ff.) shows that adding negation to the matrix clause has the effect of defocusing the embedded clause; whereas example (335a) without negation can readily be used to introduce the proposition expressed by the embedded clause in the domain of discourse, example (335b) with negation is most naturally interpreted as the denial of the presupposed truth of the embedded proposition. This means that (335b), but not (335b'), is in accordance with the generalization that wh-extraction requires the embedded clause to be part of the focus of the clause.
Since in general the addition of information to the matrix clause makes it more likely that the embedded clause is defocused, the generalization predicts that this may also have a degrading effect on wh-extraction. This may account for the contrast between the examples in (327), repeated here as (336). The verb fluisteren'to whisper' is more informative than the verb zeggen'to say' since it includes a manner component: Jan expressed his assertion in a low voice. In fact, adding a manner adverb like zachtjes'softly' in (336c) seems to have a similar degrading effect on wh-extraction, a fact that seems to have escaped attention in the literature so far.
a. | Wati | zei | Jan [Clause | dat | Marie ti | gelezen | had]? | |
what | said | Jan | that | Marie | read | had | ||
'What did Jan say that Marie had read?' |
b. | ?? | Wati | fluisterde | Jan [Clause | dat | Marie ti | gelezen | had]? |
what | whispered | Jan | that | Marie | read | had | ||
'What did Jan whisper that Marie had read?' |
c. | ?? | Wat | zei | Jan zachtjes [Clause | dat | Marie ti | gelezen | had]? |
what | said | Jan softly | that | Marie | read | had | ||
'What did Jan say softly that Marie had read?' |
Erteschik-Shir's generalization is completely in line with the findings in Verhagen (2005:124ff.): on the basis of his corpus research mentioned at the end of Subsection I, he claims that attested cases of wh-extraction differ only minimally from what he assumes to be the basic template, which he takes to be the one given in (337). He further claims that "invented examples of wh-extractions are judged worse to the degree that they deviate more from the [..] pattern [in (337)]".
XPwh - | denk(en) - | pronoun2p [CP | dat ...] | ||
XPwh - | think | you | that |
The nature of the evidence reviewed above suggests to us that each of the two approaches has something different to contribute to the description of wh-extraction. The structural approaches may be correct in claiming that wh-extraction is subject to certain structural conditions, for example, that the embedded clause is a complement of the verb in the matrix clause. The semantic approaches, on the other hand, may be correct in postulating additional conditions on the use of wh-extraction constructions, for example, that the embedded clause is the focus of attention and therefore constitutes the new information of the clause, and that as a consequence the semantic contribution of the matrix clause must be limited.
- 2012Variation and change in Germanic long-distance dependenciesUniversity of GroningenThesis
- 1973Conditions on transformationsAnderson, Stephen & Kiparsky, Paul (eds.)A festschrift for Morris HalleNew YorkHolt, Rinehart, and Winston71-132
- 1977On <i>wh</i>-movementCulicover, Peter W., Wasow, Thomas & Akmajian, Adrian (eds.)Formal syntaxNew YorkAcademic Press71-132
- 1973On the nature of Island constraintsCambridge, MAMITThesis
- 1973On the nature of Island constraintsCambridge, MAMITThesis
- 2006Bridge phenomenaEveraert, Martin & Riemdijk, Henk van (eds.)The Blackwell companion to syntax1Malden, MA/OxfordBlackwell Publishing284-294
- 2006Bridge phenomenaEveraert, Martin & Riemdijk, Henk van (eds.)The Blackwell companion to syntax1Malden, MA/OxfordBlackwell Publishing284-294
- 2006Bridge phenomenaEveraert, Martin & Riemdijk, Henk van (eds.)The Blackwell companion to syntax1Malden, MA/OxfordBlackwell Publishing284-294
- 1985V-second in GermanHaider, Hubert & Prinzhorn, Martin (eds.)Verb second phenomena in Germanic languagesDordrecht/RivertonForis Publications49-75
- 2010The syntax of GermanCambridgeCambridge University Press
- 2010The syntax of GermanCambridgeCambridge University Press
- 2006<i>Hij zei van niet, maar knikte van ja</i>: distributie en diachronie van bijwoorden van polariteit ingeleid door <i>van</i>Tabu35135-158
- 2006<i>Hij zei van niet, maar knikte van ja</i>: distributie en diachronie van bijwoorden van polariteit ingeleid door <i>van</i>Tabu35135-158
- 2006<i>Hij zei van niet, maar knikte van ja</i>: distributie en diachronie van bijwoorden van polariteit ingeleid door <i>van</i>Tabu35135-158
- 1990Relativized minimalityLinguistic Inquiry MonographCambridge, MA/LondonMIT Press
- 2005Constructions of intersubjectivity: discourse, syntax, and cognitionOxford/New YorkOxford University Press
- 2005Constructions of intersubjectivity: discourse, syntax, and cognitionOxford/New YorkOxford University Press
- 2011The syntax of DutchCambridgeCambridge University Press